Epsilon-induction
In set theory, -induction, also called epsilon-induction or set-induction, is a principle that can be used to prove that all sets satisfy a given property. Considered as an axiomatic principle, it is called the axiom schema of set induction.
The principle implies transfinite induction and recursion. It may also be studied in a general context of induction on well-founded relations.
Statement
The schema is for any given property of sets and states that, if for every set , the truth of follows from the truth of for all elements of , then this property holds for all sets. In symbols:
Note that for the "bottom case" where denotes the empty set , the subexpression is vacuously true for all propositions and so that implication is proven by just proving .
In words, if a property is persistent when collecting any sets with that property into a new set (and this also requires establishing the property for the empty set), then the property is simply true for all sets. Said differently, persistence of a property with respect to set formation suffices to reach each set in the domain of discourse.
In terms of classes
One may use the language of classes to express schemata. Denote the universal class by . Let be and use the informal as abbreviation for . The principle then says that for any ,
Here the quantifier ranges over all sets. In words this says that any class that contains all of its subsets is simply just the class of all sets.
Assuming bounded separation, is a proper class. So the property is exhibited only by the proper class , and in particular by no set. Indeed, note that any set is a subset of itself and under some more assumptions, already the self-membership will be ruled out.
For comparison to another property, note that for a class to be -transitive means
There are many transitive sets - in particular the set theoretical ordinals.
Related notions of induction
If is for some predicate , then with ,
where is defined as . If is the universal class, then this is again just an instance of the schema. But indeed if is any -transitive class, then still and a version of set induction for holds inside of .
Ordinals
Ordinals may be defined as transitive sets of transitive sets. The induction situation in the first infinite ordinal , the set of natural numbers, is discussed in more detail below. As set induction allows for induction in transitive sets containing , this gives what is called transfinite induction and definition by transfinite recursion using, indeed, the whole proper class of ordinals. With ordinals, induction proves that all sets have ordinal rank and the rank of an ordinal is itself.
The theory of Von Neumann ordinals describes such sets and, there, models the order relation , which classically is provably trichotomous and total. Of interest there is the successor operation that maps ordinals to ordinals. In the classical case, the induction step for successor ordinals can be simplified so that a property must merely be preserved between successive ordinals (this is the formulation that is typically understood as transfinite induction.) The sets are -well-founded.
Well-founded relations
For a binary relation on a set , well-foundedness can be defined by requiring a tailored induction property: in the condition is abstracted to , i.e. one always assumes in place of the intersection used in the statement above. It can be shown that for a well-founded relation , there are no infinite descending -sequences and so also . Further, function definition by recursion with can be defined on their domains, and so on.
Classically, well-foundedness of a relation on a set can also be characterized by the strong property of minimal element existence for every subset. With dependent choice, it can also be characterized by the weak property of non-existence of infinite descending chains.
Constructively weaker forms of set induction
Negated predicates
Consider set induction for a negated predicate . Denoting the class by , this amounts to the special case of above with, for any , equal to the false statement . With defined as , one has denoting . Writing for the statement that all sets are not members of the class , one now finds
Consider the equivalence of separation statements
- ,
both saying that two predicates and can not, for any value, be validated simultaneously. Applied to the antecedent, we may write
In words, a property such that there is no -minimal set for it is simply false for all sets. (A minimal for a relation is one for which there does not exist another with . Here the membership relation restricted to is considered, i.e. a minimal element with respect to is one without a .)
Consequences
Lifting one double negation in the antecedent above, one finds the antecedent is certainly implied by the stronger -statement .
Infinite descending chains
Consider a context with dependent choice and a set with the -property. Assuming the set is inhabited implies the existence of an infinite descending membership chain as sequence, i.e. a function on the naturals. So establishing the non-existence of such a chain implies .
Given the extra assumptions, the postulate of mere non-existence of infinite descending chains is relatively weak compared to set induction.
For the other direction, note that in the presence of any such membership chain function, the axiom of replacement proves existence of a set that fulfills the -property. So assuming the induction principle makes the chain existence contradictory also.
Self-membership
For a contradiction, assume there exists an inhabited set with a particular property introduced below. One studies set induction for the class of sets that are not equal to . In terms of the negated predicate, is the predicate , meaning a set that exhibits has the defining properties of . Characterized another way, is the inhabited singleton set .
The peculiar property shall be that is equal to its own singleton set, i.e. . It follows that and any set contained in also contains , i.e. . By the previous form of the principle it follow that , a contradiction. Seen differently, any empty intersection statement simplifies to just but used in the principle this does not go together with . Either way, .
It is concluded that and is simply the domain of all sets, also without any choice. In a theory with set induction, a with the described recursive property is not actually a set in the first place.
Contrapositive
For a general predicate instance of the set induction schema, taking the contrapositive reads
The contrapositive of the form with negation is constructively even weaker but it is only one double negation elimination away from the regularity claim for ,
One may also obtain a further weakened principle by strengthening the assumption to .
Classical equivalents
Relation to regularity
Classically, the above shows that set induction implies
In words, any property that is exhibited by some set is also exhibited by a "minimal set", as defined above. In terms of classes, this states that every non-empty class has a member that is disjoint from it. In first-order set theories, the common framework, the set induction principle is an axiom schema, granting an axiom for any predicate (i.e. class). In contrast, the axiom of regularity is a single axiom, formulated with a universal quantifier only over elements of the domain of discourse, i.e. over sets. If is a set and the induction schema is assumed, the above is the instance of the axiom of regularity for . Hence, assuming set induction over a classical logic (i.e. assuming the law of excluded middle), all instances of regularity hold.
In a context with an axiom of separation, regularity also implies excluded middle (for the predicates allowed in ones separation axiom). Meanwhile, the set induction schema does not imply excluded middle, while still being strong enough to imply strong induction principles, as discussed above. In turn, the schema is, for example, adopted in the constructive set theory CZF, which has type theoretic models. So within such a set theory framework, set induction is a strong principle strictly weaker than regularity. When adopting the axiom of regularity and full Separation, CZF equals standard ZF.
History
Because of its use in the set theoretical treatment of ordinals, the axiom of regularity was formulated by von Neumann in 1925. Its motivation goes back to Skolem's 1922 discussion of infinite descending chains in Zermelo set theory , a theory without regularity or replacement.
The theory does not prove all set induction instances. Regularity is classically equivalent to the contrapositive of set induction for negated statements, as demonstrated. The bridge from sets back to classes is demonstrated below.
Set induction from regularity and transitive sets
Assuming regularity, one may use classical principles, like the reversal of a contrapositive. Moreover, an induction schema stated in terms of a negated predicate is then just as strong as one in terms of a predicate variable , as the latter simply equals . As the equivalences with the contrapositive of set induction have been discussed, the task is to translate regularity back to a statement about a general class . It works in the end because the axiom of separation allows for intersection between sets and classes. Regularity only concerns intersection inside a set and this can be flattened using transitive sets.
So observe that given a class and any transitive set , one may define which has and also . The proof is by manipulation of the regularity statement for the subset of the class ,
The set may always be replaced with the class in its conclusion by the last insight. The remaining aim is to obtain a statement that also has it replaced in the antecedent.
So assume there is some so that , together with the existence of some transitive set that has as subset. An intersection may be constructed as described and it also has . Consider excluded middle for whether or not is disjoint from , i.e. . If is empty, then also and itself fulfills the principle. Otherwise, by regularity and one can proceed to manipulate the statement by replacing with as discussed. In this case, one even obtains a slightly stronger statement than the one in the previous section, since it carries the sharper information that and not just .
Transitive set existence
The existence of the required transitive sets can be postulated, the transitive containment axiom.
Existence of the stronger transitive closure with respect to membership, for any set, can also be derived from some stronger standard axioms. This needs the axiom of infinity for as a set, recursive functions on , the axiom of replacement on and finally the axiom of union. I.e. it needs many standard axioms, just sparing the axiom of powerset. In a context without strong separation, suitable function space principles may have to be adopted to enable recursive function definition.
Forms without implication
Using and double-negation elimination, the contrapositive can be further translated to the following statement:
This expresses that, for any predicate , either there is some set for which does not hold while being true for all elements of , or the predicate holds for all sets. Relating it back to the original formulation: If one can, for any set , prove that implies , which includes a proof of the bottom case , then the failure case is ruled out and, then, by the disjunctive syllogism the disjunct holds.
As refinement of excluded middle
The excluded middle for predicates can be expressed as follows: Either there exist a term for which a predicate fails, or it holds for all terms
With this, using the disjunctive syllogism, ruling out the possibility of counter-examples classically proves a property for all terms. This purely logical principle is unrelated to other relations between terms, such elementhood (or succession, see below). The induction principle is a stronger tool for the task of proving by ruling out the existence of counter-examples, and it is one often also adopted in constructive frameworks.
Comparison of epsilon and natural number induction
The transitive von Neumann model of the standard natural numbers is the first infinite ordinal. There, the binary membership relation "" of set theory exactly models the ordering of natural numbers "". Then, the principle derived from set induction complete induction.
In this section, quantifiers are understood to range over the domain of first-order Peano arithmetic , a theory with a signature including the constant symbol "", the successor function symbol "" and the addition function symbol "". Here the binary ordering relation is, for example, definable as . For any predicate , the principle reads
Making use of
- ,
complete induction is already implied by standard form of the mathematical induction schema. The latter is expressed not in terms of the decidable order relation "" but the primitive symbols,
Abstracting away the signature symbols, this can be demonstrated to still be close to set induction: Using induction, proves that every is either zero or has a computable unique predecessor with . Define a new predicate as . By design this trivially holds for zero, and so, akin to the bottom case in set induction, the implication is equivalent to just . Otherwise, and so, for positive numbers, expresses . Together one obtains
Classical equivalents
Using the classical principles mentioned above, the above may be expressed as
It expresses that, for any predicate , either there is some natural number for which does not hold, despite holding for all predecessors, or hold for all numbers.
Instead of , one may also use and obtain a related statement. It constrains the task of ruling out counter-examples for a property of natural numbers: If the bottom case is validated and one can prove, for any number , that the property is always passed on to , then this already rules out a failure case. Moreover, if a failure case exists, one can use the least number principle to even prove the existence of a minimal such failure case.
Least number principle
As in the set theory case, one may consider induction for negated predicates and take the contrapositive. After use of a few classical logical equivalences, one obtains a conditional existence claim.
Let denote the set of natural numbers validating a property . In the Neumann model, a natural number is extensionally equal to , the set of numbers smaller than . The least number principle, obtained from complete induction, here expressed in terms of sets, reads
If there is any number validating , then there (classically) is a least such number validating it such that no number is validating it. This should be compared with regularity.
For decidable and any given with , all can be tested. Moreover, adopting Markov's principle in arithmetic allows removal of double-negation for decidable in general.