Heraclitus
Heraclitus (/ˌhɛrəˈklaɪtəs/; Greek: Ἡράκλειτος Herákleitos; fl. c. 500 BC)[1] was an ancient Greek pre-Socratic philosopher from the city of Ephesus, which was then part of the Persian Empire.
Heraclitus | |
---|---|
![]() A bust of Heraclitus, from the Hall of Philosophers in the Capitoline Museums | |
Born | c. 6th century BC |
Died | c. 5th century BC Ephesus, Ionia, Delian League |
Era | Pre-Socratic philosophy |
Region | Western philosophy |
School | Ionian |
Main interests | Cosmology Process Paradox |
Notable ideas | Unity of opposites Flux Fire is the arche Logos Idios kosmos |
Influences | |
Little is known of Heraclitus's life. He wrote a single work, only fragments of which have survived. Most of the ancient stories about him are thought to be later fabrications based on interpretations of the preserved fragments. His paradoxical philosophy and appreciation for wordplay and cryptic, oracular epigrams has earned him the epithet "the obscure" since antiquity. He was considered arrogant and depressed, a misanthrope who was subject to melancholia. Consequently, he became known as "the weeping philosopher" in contrast to the ancient philosopher Democritus, who was known as "the laughing philosopher".
The central idea of Heraclitus' philosophy is the unity of opposites and the concept of change. He saw the world as constantly in flux, always "becoming" but never "being". He expressed this in sayings like panta rhei ("Everything flows") and "No man ever steps in the same river twice." This changing aspect of his philosophy is contrasted with that of the ancient philosopher Parmenides, who believed in "being" and in the static nature of reality.
Life

The main source for the life of Heraclitus is the doxographer Diogenes Laërtius; Although most of the information provided by Laertius is unreliable, the anecdote that Heraclitus relinquished the hereditary title of "king" to his younger brother may at least imply that Heraclitus was from an aristocratic family in Ephesus.[2][lower-alpha 1] As the son of aristocrats, Heraclitus appears to have had little sympathy for democracy, but it is unclear whether he was "an unconditional partisan of the rich," or "withdrawn from competing factions" - similar to Solon of Athens.[2]
In the 6th century BC, Ephesus, like other cities in Ionia, lived under the effects of both the rise of Lydia under Croesus, and his overthrow by Cyrus the Great c. 547 BC.[2] Ephesus appears to have subsequently cultivated a close relationship with the Achaemenid Empire; during the suppression of the Ionian revolt in 494 BC, Ephesus was spared and emerged as the dominant Greek city in Ionia.[2]
Heraclitus is traditionally considered to have flourished in the 69th Olympiad (504–501 BC),[3][lower-alpha 2] but this date may simply be based on a prior account synchronizing his life with the reign of Darius the Great.[2] Two extant letters between Heraclitus and Darius I, which are quoted by Diogenes Laërtius, are also later forgeries.[4] However, this date can be considered "roughly accurate" based on a fragment[lower-alpha 3] that references Pythagoras, Xenophanes, and Hecataeus as older contemporaries, which would place him near the end of the sixth century BC.[2]
Writings

Heraclitus is said to have produced a single work on papyrus,[lower-alpha 4] which has not survived; however, over 100 fragments of this work survive in quotations by other authors.[note 1] The title is unknown,[7] but many later philosophers in this period refer to this work as On Nature.[lower-alpha 5] According to Diogenes Laërtius, Heraclitus deposited the book in the Artemisium as a dedication. Laërtius also comments on the notability of the text, stating: "The book acquired such fame that it produced partisans of his philosophy who were called Heracliteans".
Kahn states:[8] "Down to the time of Plutarch and Clement, if not later, the little book of Heraclitus was available in its original form to any reader who chose to seek it out".[9] By the time of Simplicius of Cilicia, a 6th century neoplatonic philosopher, who mentions Heraclitus 32 times but never quotes from him, Heraclitus' work was so rare that it was unavailable even to Simplicius and the other scholars at the Platonic Academy in Athens.[10]
Diogenes Laertius states that the book was divided into three parts,[lower-alpha 6] but Burnet notes that "it is not to be supposed that this division is due to [Heraclitus] himself; all we can infer is that the work fell naturally into these parts when the Stoic commentators took their editions of it in hand.[11] Martin Litchfield West notes that the existing fragments do not give much of an idea of the overall structure,[12] but that the beginning of the discourse can probably be determined,[note 2] starting with the opening lines, which are quoted by Sextus Empiricus:[lower-alpha 7]
Of this Word’s being forever do men prove to be uncomprehending, both before they hear and once they have heard it. For although all things happen according to this Word they are like the unexperienced experiencing words and deeds such as I explain when I distinguish each thing according to its nature and declare how it is. Other men are unaware of what they do when they are awake just as they are forgetful of what they do when they are asleep.
Aristotle quotes part of the opening line in the Rhetoric to outline the difficulty in punctuating Heraclitus without ambiguity; he debated whether "forever" applied to "being" or to "prove".[1][lower-alpha 8] Theophrastus says (in Diogenes Laërtius) "some parts of his work [are] half-finished, while other parts [made] a strange medley".[lower-alpha 9]
The Obscure
According to Diogenes Laërtius, Timon of Phlius called Heraclitus "the Riddler" (αἰνικτής; ainiktēs), saying Heraclitus wrote his book "rather unclearly" (asaphesteron); according to Timon, this was intended to allow only the "capable" to attempt it.[lower-alpha 10] By the time of Cicero, this epithet became "The Obscure" (ὁ Σκοτεινός; ho Skoteinós) as he had spoken nimis obscurē ("too obscurely") concerning nature and had done so deliberately in order to be misunderstood.[lower-alpha 11]
Flux and unity of opposites
The hallmarks of Heraclitus' philosophy are change, or flux, and the unity of opposites. Several fragments seem to relate to this, for example "The way up is the way down," "As the same thing in us is living and dead, waking and sleeping, young and old. For these things having changed around are those, and those in turn having changed around are these" (B88) and "Cold things warm up, the hot cools off, wet becomes dry, dry becomes wet" (B126).[13]
Diogenes Laërtius summarizes Heraclitus's philosophy, stating; "All things come into being by conflict of opposites, and the sum of things (τὰ ὅλα ta hola ("the whole")) flows like a stream".[lower-alpha 12] Jonathan Barnes states that "Panta rhei, 'everything flows' is probably the most familiar of Heraclitus' sayings, yet few modern scholars think he said it."[14] Barnes observes that although the exact phrase is not ascribed to Heraclitus until the 6th century by Simplicius of Cilicia, a similar saying representing the same theory,[14] panta chorei, or "everything moves" is ascribed to Heraclitus by Plato in the Cratylus.[lower-alpha 13]
River analogy
Since Plato, Heraclitus's theory of flux has been associated with the metaphor of a flowing river, that which cannot be stepped into twice.[1] This fragment from Heraclitus's writings has survived in three different forms:[14][lower-alpha 14] One fragment[lower-alpha 15] reads: "Into the same rivers we both step and do not step; we both are and are not". Heraclitus is seemingly suggesting that not only the river is constantly changing, but we do as well, even hinting at existential questions about humankind.[15]

The German classicist and philosopher Karl-Martin Dietz interprets the metaphor as illustrating what is stable, rather than the usual interpretation of illustrating change. "You will not find anything, in which the river remains constant ... Just the fact, that there is a particular river bed, that there is a source and an estuary etc. is something, that stays identical. And this is ... the concept of a river."[16]
M. M. McCabe has argued that the three statements on rivers should all be read as fragments from a discourse. McCabe suggests reading them as though they arose in succession. The three fragments "could be retained, and arranged in an argumentative sequence".[5] In McCabe's reading of the fragments, Heraclitus can be read as a philosopher capable of sustained argument, rather than just aphorism.[5]
Strife is justice
Heraclitus' suggests the world and its various parts is kept together through the tension produced by the unity of opposites. Each substance contains its opposite, making for a continual circular exchange of generation and destruction, and motion, that results in the stability of the cosmos.[17] This can be illustrated by the quote "Even the barley-drink separates if it is not stirred."
Heraclitus called the oppositional processes ἔρις (eris), "strife", and theorized the apparently stable state, δίκη (dikê), "justice", is a harmony of it, in contrast to Anaximander who described the same as injustice.[18] Aristotle said Heraclitus disliked Homer because Homer wished that strife would leave the world, which according to Heraclitus would destroy the world; "there would be no harmony without high and low notes, and no animals without male and female, which are opposites".[lower-alpha 16] It may also explain why he dislikes Pythagoras, with the Pythagorean emphasis on harmony, but not on strife.[19]
Another of Heraclitus' famous sayings highlights this doctrine (B53): "War is father of all and king of all; and some he manifested as gods, some as men; some he made slaves, some free;" war is a creative tension that brings things into existence.[20] According to one author, "War is the central principle in Heraclitus' thought."[21]
Cosmology
Fire as arche
.jpg.webp)
Like the Milesians before him, Thales with water, Anaximander with apeiron, and Anaximenes with air, Heraclitus was considered by Aristotle to have fire as the Arche, the fundamental element that gave rise to the other elements.[22] In one fragment[lower-alpha 17], Heraclitus writes: This world-order [Kosmos], the same of all, no god nor man did create, but it ever was and is and will be: everliving fire, kindling in measures and being quenched in measures. From fire all things originate and all things return to it again in a process of eternal cycles. Heraclitus regarded the soul as a mixture of fire and water, and that fire is the noble part of the soul and water is the ignoble part, and he considered mastery of one's worldly desires to be a noble pursuit that purified the soul's fire.[23] These everlasting modifications explain his view that the cosmos was and is and will be.[24]
Heraclitus' description of a doctrine of purification of fire has also been investigated for influence from the Zoroastrian concept of Atar.[25] Many of the doctrines of Zoroastrian fire do not match exactly with those of Heraclitus, such as the relation of fire to earth, but he may have taken some inspiration from them.[25] Zoroastrian parallels to Heraclitus are often difficult to identify specifically due to a lack of surviving Zoroastrian literature from the period and mutual influence with Greek philosophy; the 9th century CE Dadestan i Denig preserves information on Zoroastrian cosmology, but also shows direct borrowings from Aristotle.[26] The interchange of other elements with fire also has parallels in Vedic literature from the same time period, such as the Kaushitaki Upanishad and Taittiriya Upanishad.[26] and West stresses that these doctrines of the interchange of elements were common throughout written work on philosophy that has survived from that period, so Heraclitus' doctrine of fire can not be definitively be said to have been influenced by any other particular Iranian or Indian influence, but may have been part of a mutual interchange of influence over time across the Ancient Near East.[27]
Logos
A fundamental term in Heraclitus is logos, an ancient Greek word with a variety of meanings; Heraclitus might have used a different meaning of the word with each usage in his book. Logos seems like a universal law that unites the cosmos, according to a fragment: "Listening not to me but to the logos, it is wise to agree (homologein) that all things are one."[lower-alpha 18] While logos is everywhere, very few people are familiar with it. Another fragment[lower-alpha 19] reads: [hoi polloi] "...do not know how to listen [to Logos] or how to speak [the truth]"[28]
Kahn stresses that Heraclitus used the word in multiple senses[8] and Guthrie observes that there is no evidence Heraclitus used it in a way that was significantly different from that in which it was used by contemporaneous speakers of Greek.[29] Guthrie considers the Logos as a public fact like a proposition or formula, though he admits that Heraclitus would not have considered these facts as abstract objects or immaterial things.[18] Another possibility is the logos referred to the book itself.
Ethos
The phrase Ethos anthropoi daimon ("man's character is [his] fate") attributed to Heraclitus has led to numerous interpretations, and might mean one's luck is related to one's character.[1] The translation of daimon in this context to mean "fate" is disputed; according to Thomas Cooksey, it lends much sense to Heraclitus's observations and conclusions about human nature in general. Other translations on offer are Charles Kahn's "a man's character is his divinity;" and Philip Wheelwright's "A man's character is his guardian divinity."[30]
Legacy and influence

Heraclitus has been the subject of numerous interpretations. According to the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Heraclitus has been seen as a "material monist or a process philosopher; a scientific cosmologist, a metaphysician and a religious thinker; an empiricist, a rationalist, a mystic; a conventional thinker and a revolutionary; a developer of logic — one who denied the law of non-contradiction; the first genuine philosopher and an anti-intellectual obscurantist."[1]
Despite this, Heraclitus' writings have exerted a wide influence on Western philosophy, including the works of Plato and Aristotle. Heraclitus is also considered a potential source for understanding the Ancient Greek religion since the discovery of the Derveni papyrus.[31]
Parmenides is generally agreed to either have influenced or have been influenced by him,[32] either as an influence or response to Heraclitean doctrines,[33] or as an extension of them.[34] Some of the writings in the Hippocratic corpus also shows signs of Heraclitean themes,[lower-alpha 20][lower-alpha 21] as do some of the surviving fragments of other pre-Socratic philosophers including Empedocles and Democritus.[32] The sophists such as Protagoras may also have been influenced by Heraclitus.[35] Many of the later Stoic, Cynic, and Skeptical philosophers considered Heraclitus an influence, and interpreted him in terms of their own doctrines.[32]
G.W.F. Hegel interpreted Heraclitus as a process philosopher, seeing the "becoming" in Heraclitus as a natural result of the ontology of "being" and "non-being" in Parmenides.[1] Martin Heidegger was also influenced by Heraclitus, as seen in his Introduction to Metaphysics. Heidegger believed that the thinking of Heraclitus and Parmenides was the origin of philosophy and misunderstood by Plato and Aristotle, leading all of Western philosophy astray.[36][32]
Heracliteans
It is unknown whether or not Heraclitus had any students in his lifetime.[32] As above, Diogenes Laertius mentions his book spawned followers called Heracliteans, including an Antisthenes who wrote a commentary on Heraclitus.[note 3] According to Aristotle, Plato knew of the teachings of Heraclitus through his follower Cratylus.
Parmenides

Parmenides, an Eleatic philosopher who was a near-contemporary of Heraclitus, proposed a doctrine of changelessness, which has been contrasted with the doctrine of flux put forth by Heraclitus.[37] Different philosophers have argued that either one of them may have substantially influenced each other, some taking Heraclitus to be responding to Parmenides, others that Parmenides is responding to Heraclitus, and some arguing that any direct chain of influence between the two is impossible to determine.[37] Although Heraclitus refers to older figures such as Pythagoras,[lower-alpha 24][lower-alpha 25] neither Parmenides or Heraclitus directly refer to each other in any surviving fragments, so any speculation on influence must be based on interpretations of the surviving fragments.[37]
Plato
Plato is the most famous philosopher who tried to reconcile Heraclitus and Parmenides; through Plato, both of these figures influenced virtually all subsequent Western philosophy. In his dialogue Cratylus, Plato presented the Heraclitean philosopher Cratylus as a linguistic naturalist, one who believes names must apply naturally to their objects.[38][39] According to Aristotle, Cratylus went a step beyond his master's doctrine and said one cannot step into the same river once.[lower-alpha 26] He took the view that nothing can be said about the ever-changing world and "ended by thinking that one need not say anything, and only moved his finger."[lower-alpha 27] To explain both characterizations by Plato and Aristotle, Cratylus may have thought continuous change warrants skepticism because one cannot define a thing that does not have a permanent nature.[40]
.jpg.webp)
Cynics
The Cynics were also influenced by Heraclitus,[41] attributing several of the later Cynic epistles to his authorship.[42]
In Stoicism
The Stoics believed major tenets of their philosophy derived from the thought of Heraclitus,[43] including a commentary by Cleanthes which has not survived.[32] Heraclitus' thought on logos influenced the Stoics, who referred to him to support their belief that rational law governs the universe.[44] While many of the later Stoics interpreted Heraclitus as having a "logos-doctrine" where the "logos[lower-alpha 28]" was a first principle that ran through all things, West[45] observes that Plato, Aristotle, Theophrastus, and Sextus Empiricus all make no mention of this doctrine, and concludes that the language and thought are "obviously Stoic" and not attributable to Heraclitus.[45] In surviving stoic writings, this is most evident in the writings of Marcus Aurelius.[46]
Explicit connections of the earliest Stoics to Heraclitus showing how they arrived at their interpretation are missing, but they can be inferred from the Stoic fragments, which Long concludes are "modifications of Heraclitus".[47] Heraclitus states, "We should not act and speak like children of our parents", which Marcus Aurelius interpreted to mean one should not simply accept what others believe. Marcus Aurelius understood the Logos as "the account which governs everything", but Burnet cautions that these modifications of Heraclitus in the Stoic fragments make it harder to use the fragments to interpret Heraclitus himself, as the Stoics ascribed their own interpretations of terms like "logos" and "ekpyrosis" to Heraclitus.[48]
In early Christianity
Although the early Christian philosophers, following the Stoics, interpreted the logos in terms of a personal God, modern scholars do not believe these associations are represented in the original thought of Heraclitus. [49] When Heraclitus speaks of "God" he does not mean a single deity as an omnipotent and omniscient or God as Creator, the universe being eternal; he meant the divine as opposed to human, the immortal as opposed to the mortal and the cyclical as opposed to the transient; to him, it is arguably more accurate to speak of "the Divine" and not of "God".[49]
Hippolytus of Rome, one of the early Church Fathers of the Christian Church identified Heraclitus along with the other Pre-Socratics and Academics as sources of heresy, and identified the logos as meaning the Christian "Word of God", such as in John 1:1, "In the beginning was the Word (logos) and the Word was God";[lower-alpha 29] however, modern scholars such as John Burnet viewed the relationship between Heraclitean logos and Johannine logos as fallacious, saying; "the Johannine doctrine of the logos has nothing to do with Herakleitos or with anything at all in Greek philosophy, but comes from the Hebrew Wisdom literature".[7] The Christian apologist Justin Martyr took a more positive view of Heraclitus. In his First Apology, he said both Socrates and Heraclitus were Christians before Christ: "those who lived reasonably are Christians, even though they have been thought atheists; as, among the Greeks, Socrates and Heraclitus, and men like them".[lower-alpha 30]
Pyrrhonian skepticism
Aenesidemus, one of the major ancient Pyrrhonist philosophers, claimed in a now-lost work that Pyrrhonism was a way to Heraclitean philosophy because Pyrrhonist practice helps one to see how opposites appear to be the case about the same thing. Once one sees this, it leads to understanding the Heraclitean view of opposites being the case about the same thing. A later Pyrrhonist philosopher, Sextus Empiricus, disagreed, arguing opposites' appearing to be the case about the same thing is not a dogma of the Pyrrhonists but a matter occurring to the Pyrrhonists, to the other philosophers, and to all of humanity.[lower-alpha 31]
Weeping philosopher

Heraclitus's influence also extends outside of philosophy. A motif found also in art and literature is Heraclitus as the "weeping philosopher" and Democritus as the "laughing philosopher," which may have originated with the Cynic philosopher Menippus,[50] and it generally references their reactions to the folly of mankind.[51][52] For example, in Lucian of Samosata's "Philosophies for Sale,"[lower-alpha 32] Heraclitus is auctioned off as the "weeping philosopher" and Democritus as the "laughing philosopher." Heraclitus also appears in Raphael's School of Athens, in which he is represented by Michelangelo.
Notes
Explanatory notes
- Some classicists and professors of ancient philosophy have disputed which of these fragments can truly be attributed to Heraclitus.[5][6]
- West suggests that the beginning may be tentatively[12] ordered as follows:[12] B1, B114, B2, B89, B30,B31,B90,B60
- Not to be confused with the cynic.[lower-alpha 22][lower-alpha 23]
Fragment numbers
- (DK B121)
- Laërtius ix.1-15
- (DK 22B40)
- Laërtius 1-15
- Laërtius ix.1-15
- Laërtius ix.1-15
- B1, Against the Mathematicians 7.132
- Rhetoric 3.1407b11
- Laërtius ix.1-15
- Laërtius
- De Finibus Bonorum et Malorum, Chapter 2, Section 15.
- Laërtius
- Plato, Cratylus, 509a (DK 22A7)
-
"On those who step into the same rivers, different and different waters flow" — Arius Didymus, quoted in Stobaeus (DK B12)
"We both step and do not step into the same, we both are and are not" — Heraclitus (commentator), Homeric Allegories (DK B49a)
"It is not possible to step into the same river twice" — Plutarch, On the E at Delphi (DK B91) - (DK 22 B49a)
- Eudemian Ethics 1235a25
- Clement, Stromtaeis (DK B30)
- (DK 22B50)
- (DK B19)
- (DK 22C1)
- (DK 22C2)
- Laërtius ix.1-15
- Diogenes Laërtius, Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers 9.15
- Laërtius
- DK B129
- Metaphysics, 987a32
- Metaphysics Books 4, section 1010a
- Lit.: word, speech, discourse
- Hippolytus Book IX, Chapter 4-5
- Justin Martyr
- Sextus Empiricus Outlines of Pyrrhonism Book I, Chapter 29, Sections 210–211
- (DK 22C5)
Citations
- Graham 2019.
- Kahn 1979, p. 1-3.
- Burnet 1892, p. 130.
- Kirk 1954, p. 1.
- McCabe 2015.
- Kahn 1979, p. 168.
- Burnet 1892, p. 133.
- Kahn 1979.
- Kahn 1979, p. 5.
- Mansfield 1999, p. 39.
- Burnet 1892, p. 132.
- West 1971, p. 113-117.
- Graham 2008, p. 175.
- Barnes 1982, p. 49.
- Warren 2014, pp. 72–74.
- Dietz, Karl-Martin (2004). Heraklit von Ephesus und die Entwicklung der Individualität. Stuttgart: Verlag Freies Geistesleben. p. 60. ISBN 978-3772512735.
- Sandywell 1996, pp. 263–265; Graham 2008, pp. 175–177.
- Guthrie 1962, p. 46.
- W. K. C. Guthrie "Pre-Socratic Philosophy" Cambridge Encyclopedia of Philosophy (1961) p. 443
- Sandywell 1996, pp. 263–265; Curd 2020, Xenophanes of Colophon and Heraclitus of Ephesus.
- Heraclitus on War by Abraham Schoener
- West 1971, p. 172-173.
- Hussey 1999, p. 111.
- Graham 2008, pp. 170–172.
- West 1971, p. 170-171.
- West 1971, p. 174-175.
- West 1971, p. 170-176.
- Warren 2014, p. 63; Sandywell 1996, p. 237.
- Guthrie 1962, p. 419.
- Remembering Heraclitus, p. 85
- Betegh 2004.
- Graham 2019, §7.
- Graham 2002.
- Nehamas 2002.
- "Structural Logos in Heraclitus and the Sophists".
- W. Julian Korab-Karpowicz, The Presocratics in the Thought of Martin Heidegger (Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang, 2016), page 58.
- Graham 2002, p. 27-30.
- Cognition in Geosciences p. 167
- Attardo, Salvatore (2002). "Translation and Humour: An Approach Based on the General Theory of Verbal Humour (GTVH)". The Translator. 8 (2): 173–194. doi:10.1080/13556509.2002.10799131. ISSN 1355-6509. S2CID 142611273.
- Logic by Wilfrid Hodges, p. 13
- The Cynics, p. 51
- J. F. Kindstrand, “The Cynics and Heraclitus”, Eranos 82 (1984), 149–78
- Long 2001, chapter 2.
- Warren 2014, p. 63.
- West 1971, p. 124-125.
- Long 2001, p. 56.
- Long 2001, p. 51.
- Burnet 1892, pp. 142–143.
- Wheelwright 1959, p. 69-73.
- Laughing and Weeping Melancholy: Democritus and Heraclitus as Emblems | SpringerLink
- "Heraclitus, Hendrick ter Brugghen, 1628". Rijksmuseum.
- "Modern Cynicism". Blackwood's Magazine: 64. 1868.
References
Ancient testimony
In the Diels–Kranz numbering for testimony and fragments of Pre-Socratic philosophy, Heraclitus is catalogued as number 22. The most recent edition of this catalogue is:
Diels, Hermann; Kranz, Walther (1957). Plamböck, Gert (ed.). Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker (in Ancient Greek and German). Rowohlt. ISBN 5875607416. Retrieved 11 April 2022.
Life and doctrines
- A1.
Laërtius, Diogenes (1925). . Lives of the Eminent Philosophers. Vol. 2:9. Translated by Hicks, Robert Drew (Two volume ed.). Loeb Classical Library.
- A2. Strabo (1929). "Book XIV". Geographica (in Ancient Greek and English). Translated by Jones, Horace Leonard; Sterrett, J. R. Sitlington. London: Heinemann. pp. 632–633.
- A3. Clement of Alexandria (1885). . Stromateis. Ante-Nicene Fathers. Translated by William Wilson – via Wikisource.
- A4. Aristotle. . Book III, section 5 (1407b) – via Wikisource.
- A5. Aristotle. "Α". Metaphysics. 984a.
- A6. Plato. Cratylus. 402a.
- A5. Aristotle. "Γ". Metaphysics. 1005b23.
- A8. Aëtius. "7". In Stobaeus (ed.). Placita. Anthologium. Vol. I. line 77.
- A9. Aristotle. "Book V". On the Parts of Animals. 645a17.
- A10. Plato. Sophist. 242d.
- A11-14. Aëtius. "13". In Stobaeus (ed.). Placita. Anthologium. Vol. II. line 8.
- A15. Aristotle. "Book II". On the Soul. 405a25.
- A16. Sextus Empiricus. "Book VII". Against the Mathematicians. 126.
- A17. Aëtius. "7". In Stobaeus (ed.). Placita. Anthologium. Vol. IV. line 2.
- A18. Aëtius. "Book V". Vetusta Placita. line 23.
- A19. Plutarch. In Defence of Oracles. 415e.
- A20. Chalcide. Scholia. 251.
- A21. Clement of Alexandria. "Book II". Stromateis. 130.
- A22. Aristotle. Eudemian Ethics. 1235a25.
- A23. Polybius. "Book IV". Histories. 20.
Fragments
- B1-2. Sextus Empiricus. "Book XVII". Against the Mathematicians. 132.
- B3. Aetius. "Book II". Placita. 21,4.
- B4. Albertus Magnus. "Book VI". De veget. 401.
- B5. Aristocritus. Theosophia. 68.
- B6. Aristotle. "Book II". Meteorology. 355a.
- B7. Aristotle. "Book 5". On Sense Perception. 443a.
- B8-9. Aristotle. "Book II". Nicomachean Ethics.
- B10-11. Pseudo-Aristotle. De Mundo. 396b.
- B12. Eusebius (1903). "Epitomae of Arius Didymus". Praeparatio evangelica. Translated by E.H. Gifford. Clarendon Press. Book XV, Chapter XVIII-XX – via Tertullian Project.
- B13. Athanaeus. "Book V". Deipnosophistae. 178F.
- B14-15. Clement of Alexandria. Protrepticus.
- B16. Clement of Alexandria. Paedagogus.
- B17-36. Clement of Alexandria. Stromateis. Translated by William Wilson – via Wikisource.
- B37. Columella. De re rustica.
- B38.
Laërtius, Diogenes (1925). . Lives of the Eminent Philosophers. Vol. 1:1. Translated by Hicks, Robert Drew (Two volume ed.). Loeb Classical Library. § 23.
- B39.
Laërtius, Diogenes (1925). . Lives of the Eminent Philosophers. Vol. 1:1. Translated by Hicks, Robert Drew (Two volume ed.). Loeb Classical Library. § 88.
- B40-46.
Laërtius, Diogenes (1925). . Lives of the Eminent Philosophers. Vol. 2:9. Translated by Hicks, Robert Drew (Two volume ed.). Loeb Classical Library.
- B47.
Laërtius, Diogenes (1925). . Lives of the Eminent Philosophers. Vol. 2:9. Translated by Hicks, Robert Drew (Two volume ed.). Loeb Classical Library. § 77.
- B49. Galen. On the knowledge of the pulse.
- B49a. Heraclitus (commentator). Homeric Allegories.
- B50-67. Hippolytus of Rome. – via Wikisource.
- B67a. Hisodsus Scholasticus (2016). Andrew Hicks (ed.). "De Anima Mundi Platonica, Commentary on Chalcides' translation of the Timaeus (dialogue)". Mediaeval Studies. 78. ISBN 978-0-88844-680-0.
- B68-69. Iamblichus. On the Mysteries).
- B70. Iamblichus. On the Soul.
- B71-75. Marcus Aurelius. Meditations.
- B78-80. Origen of Alexandria. Contra Celsum).
- B81. Philodemus. On Rhetoric).
- B82-83. Plato. Hippias major.
- B84a-84b. Plotinus. Enneads.
- B85-86. Plutarch. Life of Coriolanus.
- B87. Plutarch. On Hearing.
- B88. Plutarch. Consolation to Apollonius.
- B89. Plutarch. On Superstition.
- B90-91. Plutarch. On the E at Delphi.
- B92-93. Plutarch. On the Pythian Oracle.
- B94. Plutarch. On Exile.
- B95-96. Plutarch. Symposiacs.
- B97. Plutarch. An seni respublica gerenda sit.
- B98. Plutarch. On the face in the moon.
- B99. Plutarch. On Fire and Water.
- B100. Plutarch. Platonic Questions.
- B101. Plutarch. Against Colotes.
- B101a. Polybius. "Book 12". Histories. line 27.
- B104. Proclus. Commentary on Plato's Alcibiades.
- B106. Plutarch. Life of Camillus.
- B107. Sextus Empiricus. "Book XVII". Against the Mathematicians. 126.
Imitation
- C1. Hippocrates (1931). On Regimen. Hippocrates Collected Works. Vol. IV. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
- C2. Hippocrates (1923). On Nutrition. Hippocrates Collected Works. Vol. I. Translated by W. H. S. Jones. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
- C4. Cleanthes. Hymn to Zeus. fr. 537.
- C5. Lucian (1905). Philosophies for Sale. The works of Lucian of Samosata. Vol. 1. Translated by Fowler, H. W.; Fowler, F. G.
Modern scholarship
- Barnes, Jonathan (1982). "The Natural Philosophy of Heraclitus". The Presocratic Philosophers. London & New York: Routledge Taylor & Francis Group. pp. 43–62. ISBN 978-0-415-05079-1.
- Betegh, Gábor (2004). The Derveni papyrus : cosmology, theology, and interpretation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 9780511584435.
- Burnet, John (1892). "Heraclitus". Early Greek Philosophy. A. and C. Black. Retrieved 5 March 2022.
- Curd, Patricia (2020). "Presocratic philosophy". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Graham, D. W. (2008). "Heraclitus: Flux, Order, and Knowledge". In Curd, P.; Graham, D. W. (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 169–188. ISBN 978-0-19-514687-5.
- Graham, D. W. (2002). "Heraclitus and Parmenides". In Caston, V.; Graham, D. W. (eds.). Presocratic Philosophy: Essays in Honour of Alexander Mourelatos. Aldershot: Ashgate. pp. 27–44. ISBN 978-0-7546-0502-7.
- Graham, Daniel W. (2019). "Heraclitus". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Guthrie, W. K. C. (1962). A History of Greek Philosophy: The Earlier Presocratics and the Pythagoreans. Vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Hussey, Edward (1999). "Heraclitus". In Long, A. A. (ed.). The Cambridge Companion to Early Greek Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. pp. 88–112. ISBN 978-0-521-44667-9.
- Kahn, Charles H. (1979). The Art and Thought of Heraclitus. An Edition of the Fragments with Translation and Commentary. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-21883-2.
- Kirk, G. S. (1954). Heraclitus, the Cosmic Fragments. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Long, A. A. (2001). Stoic Studies. University of California Press. ISBN 978-0-520-22974-7.
- Mansfield, Jaap (1999). Long, A. A. (ed.). The Cambridge Companion to Early Greek Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. pp. 22–45. ISBN 978-0-521-44667-9.
- McCabe, Mary Margaret (2015-05-01), "Platonic Conversations", Oxford University Press, pp. 1–31, doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198732884.003.0001, ISBN 978-0-19-873288-4
{{citation}}
: Missing or empty|title=
(help) - Nehamas, Alexander (2002). "Parminidean Being/Heraclitean Fire". In Caston, V.; Graham, D. W. (eds.). Presocratic Philosophy: Essays in Honour of Alexander Mourelatos. Aldershot: Ashgate. pp. 45–64. ISBN 978-0-7546-0502-7.
- Sandywell, Barry (1996). Presocratic Reflexivity: The Construction of Philosophical Discourse c. 600-450 B.C.: Logological Investigations: Volume Three. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-85347-2.
- Warren, James (5 December 2014). Presocratics. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-317-49337-2.
- West, Martin L. (1971). Early Greek Philosophy and the Orient. Clarendon Press. Retrieved 6 March 2022. Chapters 4-6 deal with Heraclitus
Further reading
- Gregory, Andrew (3 January 2008). Ancient Greek Cosmogony. A&C Black. ISBN 978-1-84966-792-0.
- Hussey, Edward (1972). The Presocratics. New York: Scribner. ISBN 0684131188.
- Kirk, G. S.; Raven, J. E. (1957). The Pre-Socratic Philosophers: A Critical History with a Selection of Texts (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Mcevilley, Thomas C. (7 February 2012). The Shape of Ancient Thought: Comparative Studies in Greek and Indian Philosophies. Simon and Schuster. ISBN 978-1-58115-933-2.
- McKirahan, R. D. (2011). Philosophy before Socrates, An Introduction With Text and Commentary. Indianapolis: Hackett. ISBN 978-1-60384-183-2.
- Mikalson, Jon (24 June 2010). Greek Popular Religion in Greek Philosophy. OUP Oxford. ISBN 978-0-19-957783-5.
- Mitchell, John Malcolm (1911). Encyclopædia Britannica. Vol. 13 (11th ed.). pp. 309–310. .
- Mourelatos, Alexander, ed. (1993). The Pre-Socratics : a collection of critical essays (Rev. ed.). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-0-691-02088-4.
- Naddaf, Gerard (2005). The Greek Concept of Nature. SUNY Press. ISBN 978-0791463734.
- Schofield, Malcolm; Nussbaum, Martha Craven, eds. (1982). Language and logos : studies in ancient Greek philosophy presented to G. E. L. Owen. Cambridge: Cambridge U.P. ISBN 978-0-521-23640-9.
- Stamatellos, Giannis (1 February 2012). Plotinus and the Presocratics: A Philosophical Study of Presocratic Influences in Plotinus' Enneads. State University of New York Press. ISBN 978-0-7914-8031-1.
- Wheelwright, Philip (1959). Heraclitus. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
- Wright, M. R. (1985). The Presocratics: The main Fragments in Greek with Introduction, Commentary and Appendix Containing Text and Translation of Aristotle on the Presocratics. Bristol: Bristol Classical Press. ISBN 978-0-86292-079-1.
External links
Library resources about Heraclitus |
By Heraclitus |
---|
Works related to Fragments of Heraclitus at Wikisource
Quotations related to Heraclitus at Wikiquote
Media related to Heraclitus at Wikimedia Commons
- Stamatellos, Giannis. "Heraclitus of Ephesus: Life and Work". Retrieved 2007-10-12.